perm filename CHAP5[4,KMC]7 blob
sn#026714 filedate 1973-02-27 generic text, type T, neo UTF8
00100 A SYMBOL-PROCESSING THEORY OF THE PARANOID MODE
00200
00300 K.M. COLBY
00400
00500
00600 Our theory , a conjunction of hypotheses and auxiliary
00700 assumptions, postulates a structure or organization of interacting
00800 symbolic procedures. These procedures and their interactions are
00900 supported by a number of auxiliary assumptions and presuppositions as
01000 will become apparent as the story unfolds.
01100
01200
01300 We presuppose a schema of action and non-action which takes
01400 the form of a practical inference:
01500 AN AGENT A WANTS SITUATION S TO OBTAIN
01600 A BELIEVES THAT IN ORDER FOR S TO OBTAIN , A MUST DO X
01700 THEREFORE A PLANS, TRIES OR PROCEEDS TO DO X.
01800 An agent is taken here to be any intentionalistic system, person ,
01900 procedure or strategy having purposes. To do means to produce,
02000 prevent or allow something to happen. We presuppose the agent's power
02100 to do X. X can be multiple sequential or concurrent actions and
02200 includes mental action (e.g. deciding) as well as physical
02300 action(e.g.talking). It is also presupposed in this action-schema
02400 that , in doing X, A receives feedback as to whether S is coming
02500 about, i.e. whether doing X is successful or not in obtaining S.
02600
02700 It is established clinical knowledge that the phenomena of
02800 the paranoid mode can be found associated with a variety of physical
02900 disorders. For example, paranoid thinking can be found in patients
03000 with head injuries, hyperthyroidism hypothyroidism, uremia,
03100 pernicious anemia, cerebral arteriosclerosis, congestive heart
03200 failure, malaria and epilepsy. Also drug intoxications due to
03300 alcohol, amphetamines, marihuana and LSD can be accompanied by the
03400 paranoid mode. To account for the association of paranoid thought
03500 with these physical states of illness, one might be tempted to
03600 hypothesize that a mental system attempts to explain the illness
03700 state by constructing persecutory beliefs blaming other human agents
03800 for causing the ill-being of the disease state. But before
03900 making such an explanatory move, we must consider the elusive
04000 distinction between reasons and causes in explanations of human
04100 behavior.
04200
04300
04400 When human action is to be explained, confusion easily arises
04500 between appealing to reasons and appealing to causes, as has been
04600 discussed in detail by Toulmin [ ]. One view of the association of
04700 [TOULMIN REF.-EXPLANATION IN THE BEHAVIORAL SCIENCES,BORGER R.AND CIOFFI,
04800 F.,(EDS.), CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS, N.Y.,(1971). ]
04900 the paranoid mode with physical disorders might be that the physical
05000 illness simply causes the paranoia ,through some unknown mechanism,
05100 at a hardware level beyond the influence of the procedures of mental
05200 processes and beyond voluntary self-control. That is, the resultant paranoid
05300 process represents something that happens to a person as patient,
05400 not something that he does as an active agent. Another view is that
05500 the paranoid mode can be explained in terms of reasons,
05600 justifications which describe an agent's intentions and beliefs. If
05700 we consider a person to be the agent, does he recognize, monitor and control what he is
05800 doing or trying to do? Or does it just happen to him automatically
05900 without conscious deliberation? This question raises a third view,
06000 namely that unrecognized reasons, ` compiled' versions of the program
06100 now inacessible to voluntary control, can function like causes. Once
06200 brought to consciousness in an `interpreted' version such reasons can
06300 be modified voluntarily by the agent, as a language user, reflexively talking to and
06400 instructing himself. This giving oneself orders contrasts with an agent's inability to
06500 modify causes which lie beyond the influence of self-criticism and
06600 change through internal language-based argumentation. Timeworn conundrums about
06700 concepts of free-will, determinism, responsibility, consciousness and
06800 the powers of mental action here plague us unless we stick closely to
06900 our computer analogy which makes a clear and useful distinction
07000 between hardware, interpreter and programs.
07100
07200 Each of these three views provides a serviceable perspective
07300 depending on how a disorder is to be explained and corrected. When
07400 paranoid processes occur during amphetamine intoxication they might
07500 be viewed as biochemically caused and beyond the patient's ability to
07600 control volitionally through internal reprogramming dialogues with
07700 himself. When a paranoid moment occurs in a normal person it can be
07800 viewed as having a reason or justification. If the paranoid belief
07900 is recognized as such,the agent has the power to revise or reject it.
08000 Between these extremes of drug-induced paranoid processes and the
08100 self-correctible paranoid moments of the normal person, lie cases of
08200 paranoid personalities, paranoid psychoses and the paranoid mode
08300 associated with the major psychoses (schizophrenic and
08400 manic-depressive). Current opinion has it that the major psychoses
08500 are a consequence of unknown hardware causes and are beyond
08600 deliberate voluntary control. But what are we to conclude about
08700 paranoid personalities and paranoid psychoses where no hardware
08800 disorder is suspected? Are they to be considered patients to whom
08900 something is mechanically happening or are they agents whose behavior is a
09000 consequence of what they do? Or are they both agent and patient
09100 depending on on how we view the self-modifiability of their symbolic processing?
09200 In these enigmatic cases we shall take the position that in normal, neurotic and psychotic
09300 paranoid processes (independent of the major psychoses) the paranoid
09400 mode represents something that happens to a man as a consequence both
09500 of something he does and something he undergoes. Thus he is both
09600 agent and patient whose mental processes have powers to do and capacities
09700 to undergo.
09800
09900
10000 From this standpoint we postulate a duality between reasons
10100 and causes. That is, just as in an algorithm a procedure can serve as
10200 an input argument to another procedure, a reason can function as a
10300 cause in one context and as a justification in another. When a final
10400 cause, such as a consciously conceptualized intention, guides
10500 efficient causes we can say that human action is non-determinate
10600 since it is self-determinate. Thus the power to make decisions freely
10700 and to change one's mind is non-illusory. When a reason is recognized
10800 to function as a cause and is acessible, it may be changed by another
10900 procedure which takes it as an argument. In this sense a two-levelled
11000 system involving an interpreter and its programs is self- changeable
11100 and self-correcting, within limits.
11200
11300 The major processes we postulate to govern the paranoid mode
11400 involve an organization of symbol-processing procedures at one level
11500 governed by an interpreter at another level. We shall sketch the
11600 operations of this organization briefly. First:
11700 (1) The interpreter executes a `consciencing' procedure which
11800 judges an action or state of the self to be wrong according to criteria of
11900 right-wrong sanctioning beliefs. A censuring process attempts to find and blame
12000 an agent for the wrong.
12100 (2)The interpreter attemts a simulation of assigning blame to
12200 the self. If the self accepts blame, the trial simulation detects an affect-signal
12300 of shame warning of an eventual undergoing of humiliation. The detection in the simulation serves as an
12400 anticipatory warning not to actually execute this procedure since it will
12500 result in the painful re-experiencing of a negative affect-state of
12600 humiliation.
12700 (3) An alternative procedure of assigning blame to others is
12800 next simulated and found not to eventuate in a painful affect-state.
12900 Hence it is executed. It operates to deny that the self is to blame
13000 for a wrong and to project blame onto other human agents. Now it is
13100 not the self who is responsible for a wrong but it is that the self is
13200 wronged by others. This procedure is inefficient and only partially effective as an
13300 escape since the outward behavior it generates results in the self still undergoing criticisms and condemnations.
13400 which can lead to shame and humiliation.Only the locus of the censure has been shifted from the self to others.
13500
13600 (4)Since others are now believed to have intentions to wrong
13700 the self, procedures for the detection of malevolence in the input
13800 from others, as individuals or as part of a conspiracy, achieve a
13900 first priority.
14000
14100
14200 (5) If the input procedures succeed in detecting malevolence,
14300 output strategies are executed in an attempt to reduce the other's
14400 malevolent effects.
14500 (6) Finally an evaluation is made regarding the success or
14600 failure of the output procedures.
14700 The above description attempts to summarize in somewhat loose
14800 prose a complex series of postulated interactions in an organization
14900 of symbol-processing procedures. The details of these procedures
15000 and their interactions will be made explicit when the algorithm is
15100 described (see p ). The theory is circumscribed in that it attempts
15200 to explain only certain phenomena of a particular type of episode.It does not attempt to explain, for
15300 example, why the censuring process condemns particular actions or
15400 states as wrongs nor how any of these procedures develop over time in
15500 the person's socialization experience. Thus it does not provide an
15600 ontogenetic explanation of how an organization of processes came to
15700 be the way it is. The model offers an explanation only of how the
15800 organization operates as a genesis in the present.
15900 Some evidence bearing on the postulated processes will now be
16000 discussed. The processes of (4),which attempt to cope with a
16100 malevolent other, receive evidential support from observations of
16200 normal, neurotic and psychotic paranoias. The agent may report
16300 his self-monitoring directly to an observer commenting that his, for example, hostile remarks are
16400 intended to retaliate for a believed wrong at the hands of the other.
16500 ("I want him to feel bad and to leave me alone".) The output actions
16600 of the paranoid mode can be grouped into reducing persecution by
16700 retribution or by withdrawal. Retribution is intended to drive the
16800 other away while withdrawal removes the self from the sphere of the
16900 other. We are not aware of any experimental evidence bearing on this
17000 point and perhaps the clinical and everday obsevations are sufficient
17100 enough not to require any.
17200 The intensive scan for malevolence postulated in (3) has both
17300 clinical and experimental evidence in its behalf. Clinicians are
17400 familiar with the darting eye-movements of psychotic paranoids.
17500 Patients themselves report their hypervigilance as intended to detect
17600 signs of malevolence. Silverman [ ] and Venables [ ] have reported
17700 experiments indicating that paranoid schizophrenics more extensively
17800 scan their visual fields and have a greater breadth of attention than
17900 other schizophrenic patients.
18000 In considering the processes postulated in (2) and (1),
18100 direct evidence is hard to come by. Projection is a century-old
18200 concept which has been used to account for the common clinical
18300 observation that paranoid patients accuse others of actions and
18400 states which hold true for themselves according an outside observer.
18500 As Newton said about Leibniz 300 years ago `he himself is guilty of
18600 what he complains of in others'.(The details of this paranoid clash can be found in []).
18700 A process of projection has also been offered to account for the particular selectivity involved in
18800 the hypersensitivity to criticism. That is, why does a man believe
18900 others will ridicule him about his appearance unless some part of
19000 himself believes his appearance to be defective. An alternative view
19100 is that the selectivity stems from the agent observing how others in
19200 his subculture are ridiculed and expects the same to be applied to
19300 him.
19400 The obscurity of the relation between what the self expects
19500 as malevolence and the self's own properties is well illustrated in
19600 hypotheses which attempt to explain the paranoid mode as a
19700 consequence of homosexual conflict. It has long been observed that
19800 some (not all) paranoid patients are excessively concerned with the
19900 topic of homosexuality. Several studies of hospitalized paranoid
20000 schizophrenics show them to be preoccupied with homosexuality far
20100 more than the nonpsychotic controls.(See Klaf and Davis [ ],etc) Such
20200 evidence may be interpreted as having generative implications for certain
20300 cases. In a more general theory , if homosexual interests are
20400 evaluated by the censuring process as wrong, then this genesis
20500 becomes plausible but no more than that. It is also plausible that an
20600 agent expects to be accused of homosexuality because in his community
20700 that is a common means of ridicule regardless of the actual nature of
20800 the transgression determined by the censuring process.
20900 It is obvious that something ordinarily called conscience
21000 regulates human behaviour. But are distorted censuring and blaming processes
21100 actually the generative core of the pathological procedures of
21200 the paranoid mode? Heilbrun and Norbert have shown that paranoid
21300 schizophrenics are more sensitive to maternal censure as measured by
21400 the disruption of a cognitive task by a tape-recording of a mother
21500 censuring her son. [ ]
21600 (Further discussion of evidence here)